Exploring a Scientific Framework of Consciousness while revisiting Ancient Wisdom
Aashutosh Kulakarni
Exploring a Scientific Framework of Consciousness while revisiting Ancient Wisdom
The feeling
of being conscious and sentient is most familiar to each of us and fundamental
to life itself. We have become so accustomed to it that we seldom ponder its
bizarreness and yet, it is the greatest mystery that life has to offer. How are
we chunks of flesh and bone with a peculiar yet incredibly distinct inner life?
Why are we conscious at all? There is no greater quest in life than to dwell on
this deep mystery, to investigate it, and attempt to unravel it.
A lifetime
of scientific conditioning seems to hint to us that consciousness is created in
the brain, by the brain. After all, isn’t the world made up of matter and
energy, so our consciousness is too? Well, it may seem surprising for some to
learn that not only does science have no real evidence for this narrative, but it
also has no clue where to start looking for consciousness! All it can observe
is a flutter of neural activity that correlate to specific conscious
experiences, but correlation is not causality. Despite this, staunch materialist
philosophers like Daniel Dennett at Tufts University insist that consciousness
isn’t really all that important since it can be nothing but a by-product of our
brains and as a result, there really is no deeper meaning to life. This notion,
however, that consciousness is but an epiphenomenon of the brain isn’t
questioned as much as it should be. Materialism analyses the world objectively
and breaks down the objects of the world down to matter. The grave mistake in
treating consciousness as any other object in the world is that consciousness
itself is not an object to be perceived. Instead, it would be more accurately
described as that which perceives everything! As the 19th century
German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer once stated, “Materialism is the
philosophy of the subject who forgets to take account of himself.” Now that I
have, with the support of Schopenhauer, thrown doubt over conventional
material philosophy, it is worth considering what the nature of the problem really
is.
Often, problems
of consciousness that are investigated deal with both the mind and
consciousness. These are commonly termed as the ‘Easy problems of consciousness’.
Take, for example, the question of our attention. How are we able to
consciously focus our attention onto a specific task? The answer to this
question is one of objective processing. A study of the neural patterns and
pathways that are involved in focusing attention can provide a sufficient explanation.
Or how do we access our memories? Again, identifying the parts of the brain associated
with memory and the corresponding neural mechanisms can provide us with an
accepted solution. Underlying all the easy problems, however, is a problem that
is deeper on a scientific and philosophical level. This is the Hard Problem of
Consciousness.
A term that
was first coined by David Chalmers, an Australian philosopher who resides at
NYU, the hard problem refers to the very feeling of consciousness itself, not
merely its functional attributes. Why do we have a subjective experience of
consciousness at all? Why aren’t we just chunks of thinking and processing
flesh that can robotically interact with the world without inner lives? Why
does consciousness feel like anything at all? These deep questions have quite
distinct differences from the easy problems. The easy problems seek to question
how specific conscious experiences are correlated to the brain. The hard
problem asks not only how we are conscious at all, but more importantly, why we
are conscious. The materialist philosophy falls treacherously short of
providing any meaningful answer to this question. Neural mechanisms in the
brain provide not a shred of an explanation as to why it generates a subjective
experience. In an interview with Serious Science, David Chalmers states that
the hard problem is “ultimately a question for science, but it’s a question
which right not, our scientific methods don’t have a very good handle on. So at
least for now, it's a central question for philosophy.” What he implies is that
the reductionist, material approach nature of most science makes it quite
unequipped to deal with the hard problem. Therefore, since all of us are
conscious (hopefully), we could use philosophy to navigate this problem better
than science can, for now.
If science
could avoid the typical materialist route, perhaps a worthwhile scientific
theory of consciousness can be conjured up. Conveniently, this has been done. Introducing,
Integrated Information Theory (IIT), a new scientific hope! The key to this theory,
as the name suggests is integrated information. Integrated information, simply
put, is a measure of the back-and-forth interactions between component parts of
a system. The maximum amount of integrated information that a system has,
denoted by Φ is equivalent to the consciousness that a system possesses. What this
means is that when systems, of any sort, have bits of information being shared
between parts of the system that influence each other, there is a certain
degree of consciousness associated with the system. The resulting claim of IIT
is that our brains are not the only locations of consciousness but every single
interacting system, like my laptop or the internet, is conscious to an extent.
While this
idea may seem bizarre, it leads to a serious line of philosophical thinking
known as panpsychism, that figures like David Chalmers and the neuroscientist
Christof Koch are strong proponents of. Unlike materialism, which argues that
consciousness emerges from physical matter and, on the other hand, dualism
which proposes that consciousness and matter are separate entities, panpsychism
postulates that like matter, consciousness is also a fundamental and ubiquitous
feature of reality. Little ‘cells’ of consciousness exist everywhere and
pervade the entire universe. Under the right conditions and interactions, they
are sufficiently complex enough to generate a conscious experience as intricate
and subjective as ours. Panpsychism and IIT try to unify consciousness as being
integrated all the way down to the most fundamental levels. Take an atom for
example. The atom that consists of its subatomic particles has its own
interactions within it as the electron orbits the nucleus. Each atom, therefore,
has its own tiny spark of consciousness. Hence consciousness must pervade the
entire material universe.
Both IIT and
panpsychism face shortcomings, however. The philosopher John Searle, in a review
of Christof Koch’s book ‘Consciousness’, brings up the circularity problem faced
by IIT. He argues that “you can’t explain consciousness by saying it consists
of information, because information exists only relative to consciousness.” What
this means is that information itself can only have value to a conscious
observer, therefore consciousness itself cannot be dependent on information. A
second shortcoming of IIT appears in the mathematical predictions it makes on
the degree of consciousness possessed by objects. Scott Aaronson, a computer
scientist at the University of Texas Austin, revealed that IIT’s mathematics
predicts information systems such as a compact disc to be more conscious than
humans are. To any sane person, this prediction seems absurd! It also brings up
the problem of solipsism, which is the idea that we can only ever be sure of
the existence of our individual self and consciousness. Therefore, if I can’t
even be sure if other humans are conscious, how am I to believe that a CD can
be more conscious than I? Christof Koch thinks that a ‘consciousness meter’ can
be devised to tackle this problem. A meter that uses a ‘zap and zip’ method,
which involves zapping brains with magnetic pulses and zips the entire brains
response to a single number. However, even if realized, this device would again
be dealing with the easy problems of consciousness, that relate to neural
capability and its correlation to conscious experience. It would not shed more
insight into the hard problem and there seems no way to use it on inanimate objects.
Furthermore, panpsychism is
plagued with the combination problem. There is no explanation for the
unification of the proposed tiny, individual cells of consciousness into a
single human consciousness. Why don’t I have a million subjective experiences
instead of just one? Finally, IIT, despite its attempts, is not an entirely
convincing answer to the hard problem as it merely suggests that interacting
parts of a system has some degree of consciousness. It does not offer a
convincing answer to the real question, which is why consciousness feels the
way it does at all. Why does information give rise to a subjective experience? These
questions seem to have no plausible solution in sight through the framework of
IIT. Since I do not find IIT to be a satisfying answer, I will turn towards
more ancient philosophy and spiritual insights, if you will.
Philosophers
and scientists intrigued by the hard problem often develop an interest towards
Buddhism and rightfully so. Christof Koch, in a conversation with the Dalai
Lama, found that some of his views on panpsychism matched the Buddhist views on
consciousness. The late Buddhist master Traleg Kyabgon Rinpoche stated that the
mind, while it is empty like all objects in the universe, is also luminous. This
luminosity is felt as consciousness. Soto Zen Buddhism also asserts that consciousness
and sentience is present everywhere in varying degrees. This idea follows a
similar vein to the proposal of IIT, that consciousness exists at
different degrees in every interacting system in the universe. However,
Buddhism diverges by insisting that the key to the hard problem is not
scientific analysis, but meditation. Meditation leads to an understanding of
the mind and eventually, when one attains Nirvana (liberation), the answers to all
questions of life become clear. While I don’t doubt this, Buddhism emphasizes compassion
and meditation over intellectual inquiry. To a mind that craves a bit of
philosophical satisfaction, this seems underwhelming.
The next system
of philosophy that I will consider is Vedanta, one of the six orthodox schools
of Hinduism. The central theme of Vedanta, specifically Advaita (Non-dual)
Vedanta is that consciousness encompasses everything in the universe. While IIT
and panpsychism postulate that consciousness pervades the universe at varying
levels, Vedanta goes a few steps further and declares that nothing exists apart
from consciousness. The consciousness that Vedanta refers to is not just the
localized consciousness that we feel, but a larger, transcendent and non-local
consciousness. Our subjective consciousness is simply a reflection in the mind
of the transcendental consciousness. What I find very valuable in Vedanta is
that it clearly distinguishes the mind and consciousness itself. Almost all
of neuroscience and modern philosophy of mind does not make an effort towards this
distinction. While the mind certainly does process conscious experiences,
Vedanta claims that the mind itself is merely an object of our consciousness. Consider
the nature of our minds. Our minds are oceans of constant change. Our thoughts
vary every second, our emotions are malleable to the slightest of forces and our
tendencies have changed drastically over years. And yet, our sentience itself
and the very feeling of life has always been the same. Our consciousness on its
own, without association to the changing mind, has been unwavering. Moreover,
deep sleep or lack of awareness under anesthesia is considered a ‘disappearance’
of consciousness. Vedanta on the other hand makes the claim that these
states are not absences of conscious experience, but a consciousness experience of
absence. This stunning claim suggests that it is the mind that is ‘switched
off’ and as a result, there are no objects to be experienced.
To further
this point, consider the easy and hard problems of consciousness. The easy
problems all boil down to conscious mental states of the mind. The hard
problem however is not a problem of consciousness and the mind, it is a
problem of only consciousness. Vedanta asserts that this underlying
sentience and consciousness is our true nature. It encourages us to investigate
every experience that we have and begin to see this as an indubitable fact of every
second of our lives. It also offers a path, like Buddhism, to realize this
truth in our lives.
Going back
to a quote from David Chalmers who mentioned that “at least for now, (the hard
problem) is a central question for philosophy.” I would argue that it will forever be a question for philosophy that science will always
fall short of answering. The nature of science is to study what we can perceive
from world. To reiterate the Vedantic perspective, consciousness is not an
object to be perceived, it is that which perceives everything. Therefore, the very
nature of science makes it destined to be erroneous!
Ultimately, I turn towards spirituality to lead this highest quest of life, not science and not even conventional western philosophy. I will end by quoting Swami Sarvapriyananda, a Hindu monk who resides in Manhattan and has facilitated the conversation regarding consciousness tirelessly. In response to the growing attempt to develop conscious Artificial Intelligence, he states: “The basis of AI is that consciousness is material and can be infinitely divided and manipulated. The basis of spirituality is that consciousness is not material. It is indivisible and transcendent and that is where we must seek to find peace.”
Comments
Post a Comment